Philosophical Musings (1)
Sam Vaknin

 

150 philosophical articles and essays by the same author - available!

http://www.geocities.com/vaksam/culture.html

This letter constitutes a permission to reprint or mirror any and all of the materials mentioned or linked to herein subject to appropriate credit and linkback.

The Sample Articles (please scroll down to review them):

I. The Aborted Contract
II. The Basic Dilemma of the Artist
III. The Fourth Law of Robotics
IV. The Impeachment of the President of the USA


Author: Sam Vaknin

Contact Info: [email protected]; [email protected]

AUTHOR BIO:

Sam Vaknin has a combined doctorate in Physics and Philosophy.

He is an economic and political columnist in many periodicals in a few
countries and a published and awarded author of short fiction and reference
books in Hebrew, English and Macedonian in Israel, Macedonia and the Czech
Republic.

He has collaborated with Israeli psychologists and criminologists in the
study of personality disorders and is the author of "Malignant Self Love -
Narcissism Revisited" (available from Barnes and Noble and, as an e-book,
from Booklocker, eBooksonthe.net, SoftLock, MightyWords and from CyberRead).

He is the editor of the Mental Health Disorders category in the Open
Directory Project and the editor of the Narcissistic Personality Disorder
topic in Suite101.

He is serving currently as the Economic Advisor to the Government of
Macedonia.

His new book "After the Rain - How the West Lost the East" is available from
Barnes and Noble and, as an e-book, from Booklocker, eBooksonthe.net,
MightyWords, SoftLock and from CyberRead.

Full CV is available at: http://www.geocities.com/vaksam/cv.html

Web addresses: http://narcissism.cjb.net , http://personality.cjb.net ,
http://musings.cjb.net , http://economics.cjb.net,
http://www.ce-review.org/authorarchives/vaknin_archive/vaknin_main.html

Email address: [email protected] or [email protected]



The Aborted Contract
By: Dr. Sam Vaknin

The issue of abortion is emotionally loaded and this often makes for poor,
not thoroughly thought out arguments. The questions: "Is abortion immoral"
and "Is abortion a murder" are often confused. The pregnancy (and the
resulting foetus) are discussed in terms normally reserved to natural
catastrophes (force majeure, in legal lingo). At times, the embryo is
compared to cancer: after all, they are both growths, clusters of cells.
The difference, of course, is that no one contracts cancer willingly
(except, to some extent, smokers --but, then they gamble, not contract).
When a woman engages in voluntary sex, does not use contraceptives and gets
pregnant - one can say that she signed a contract with her foetus. A
contract entails the demonstrated existence of a reasonably (and reasonable)
free will. If the fulfilment of the obligations in a contract could be
life-threatening - it is fair and safe to assume that no rational free will
was involved. No reasonable person would sign or enter such a contract.
Judith Jarvis Thomson argued convincingly ("A Defence of Abortion") that
pregnancies that are the result of forced sex (rape being a special case) or
which are life threatening should or could, morally, be terminated. Using
the transactional language : the contract was not entered to willingly or
reasonably and, therefore, is null and void. Any actions which are intended
to terminate it and to annul its consequences should be legally and morally
permissible.
The same goes for a contract which was entered into against the express will
of one of the parties and despite all the reasonable measures that the
unwilling party adopted to prevent its crystallization. If a mother uses
contraceptives in a manner intended to prevent pregnancy, it is as good as
saying: I do not want to sign this contract, I am doing my reasonable best
not to sign it, if it is signed - it is contrary to my express will. There
is little legal (or moral) doubt that such a contract should be voided.
Much more serious problems arise when we study the other party to these
implicit agreements: the embryo. To start with, it lacks consciousness (in
the sense that is needed for signing an enforceable and valid contract).
Can a contract be validated even if one of the "signatories" lacked this
sine qua non trait? In the absence of consciousness, there is little point
in talking about free will. So, is the contract not a contract at all?
Does it not reflect the intentions of the parties?
The answer is in the negative. The contract between a mother and her foetus
is derived from the larger Social Contract. Society - through its
apparatuses - stands for the embryo the same way that it represents minor,
the mentally retarded and the insane. Society steps in - and has the
recognized right and moral obligation to do so - whenever the powers of the
parties to a contract (implicit or explicit) are not balanced. It protects
small citizens from big monopolies, the physically weak from the thug, the
tiny opposition from the mighty administration, the barely surviving radio
station from the claws of the devouring State mechanism. It also has the
right and obligation to intervene, intercede and represent the unconscious :
this is why euthanasia is absolutely forbidden without the consent of the
dying person. There is not much difference between the embryo and the
comatose.
A contract states the rights of the parties. It assumes the existence of
parties which are "moral personhoods" or "morally significant persons" - in
other words, persons who are holders of rights and can demand from us to
respect these rights. The contract explicitly elaborates some of these
rights and leaves others unmentioned because of the presumed existence of
the Social Contract. The contract assumes that there is a social contract
which includes the parties to the contract and which is universally known
and, therefore, implicitly incorporated in every contract. Thus, an
explicit contract can talk about the right of a person to a certain property
but it will fail to mention that person's rights to life, free speech,
enjoying the lawful fruits of his property and, in general to a happy life.
There is little debate that the Mother is a morally significant person and
that she is a rights-holder. All born humans are and, more so, all adults
above a certain age. But what about the unborn foetus?
One approach is that the embryo has no rights until certain conditions are
met and only upon their fulfilment is he transformed into a morally
significant person. Opinions differ as to what are the conditions
rationality, a morally meaningful and valued life are some of the oft used
criteria. The fallibility of this venue is easy to demonstrate: children
are irrational - is this a licence to commit infanticide?
A second approach says that a person has the right to life because he
desires it.
But then what about chronic depressives who desire to die - do we have the
right to terminate their miserable lives? The good part of life (and,
therefore, the differential and meaningful test) is in the experience - not
in the desire to experience. Another variant says that a person has the
right to life because once his life is terminated - his experiences will
cease. So, how should we judge the right to life of someone who constantly
endures bad experiences (and, as a result, harbours a death wish)?
Having reviewed the above arguments and counter-arguments, Don Marquis goes
on (in "Why Abortion is Immoral", 1989) to offer a sharper and more
comprehensive criterion: terminating a life is morally wrong because a
person has a future filled with value and meaning, similar to ours.
But the whole debate is unnecessary. There is no conflict between the
rights of a Mother and those of her foetus because there is never a conflict
between parties to an agreement. By signing an agreement, the Mother gave
up some of her rights and limited the other. This is normal practice in
contracts: they represent compromises, optimization - not maximization. The
rights of the foetus are an inseparable part of the contract which the
mother signed voluntarily and reasonably. They are derived from the Mother'
s behaviour. Getting willingly pregnant (or assuming the risk of getting
pregnant by not using contraceptives reasonably) - is the behaviour which
validates and ratifies a contract between her and the foetus. Many times
contracts are the result of behaviour and witnessed by it, rather than by a
piece of signed paper. Numerous contracts are verbal or behavioural. Other
contracts, though implicit, are as binding as any of their written
counterparts. Legally (and morally) the situation is crystal clear the
Mother signed some of her rights away in this contract. Even if she regrets
it - she cannot claim her rights back by annulling the contract
unilaterally. No contract can be annulled this way - the consent of both
parties is required. Many times we realize that we have entered a bad
contract, but there is nothing much that we can do about it. These are the
rules of the game.
Thus the two questions: (a) can the contract be annulled and, if so (b) in
which circumstances - can be easily settled using modern contract law. Yes,
a contract can be annulled and voided if signed under duress, involuntarily,
or if one of the parties made a reasonable and full scale attempt to prevent
its signature, thus expressing its inviolable will not to sign the contract.
It is also terminated or voided if it would be unreasonable to expect one of
the parties to see it through. Rape, contraception failure, life
threatening situations all are such cases.
This could be argued against by saying that, in case of economic hardships,
or instance, the damage to the Mother's future is certain. Her value
filled, meaningful future is granted - and so is the detrimental effect that
the foetus will have on it, once born. This certainty cannot be balanced by
the UNCERTAIN value-filled future life of the embryo. Always, preferring an
uncertain good to a certain evil is morally wrong. But surely this is a
quantitative matter - not a qualitative one. Certain, limited aspects of
the rest of the Mother's life will be adversely effected (and can be
ameliorated by society's helping hand and intervention) if she does have the
baby. The decision not to have it is both qualitatively and qualitatively
different. It is to deprive the unborn of all the aspects of all his future
life - in which he might well have experienced happiness, values and
meaning.
The questions whether the foetus is a Being or a growth of cells, conscious
in any manner or utterly unconscious, able to value his life and to want
them - are all but irrelevant. He has the potential to lead a happy,
meaningful, value-filled life, similar to ours, very much as a one minute
old baby does. The contract between him and his Mother is a service
provision contract. She will provide him with goods and services that he
requires in order to materialize his potential. It sounds very much like
many other human contracts. Take education: children do not appreciate its
importance or value its potential - still, it is enforced upon them because
we, who are capable of those feats, want them to have the tools that they
will need in order to develop their potential. In this and many other
respects, the human pregnancy continues well into the fourth year of life
(physiologically it continues in to the second year of life). Is the
location of the pregnancy (in uterus, in vivo) to determine its future? Why
should the Mother be denied her right to terminate the pregnancy after the
foetus emerges and the pregnancy continues outside her womb? Even after
birth, the woman's body is the main source of food to the baby and, in any
case, she has to endure physical hardship. Why not extend the woman's
ownership of her body and right to it further in time and space?
Contracts to provide goods and services (always at a personal cost to the
provider) are the commonest of contracts. We open a business. We sell a
software, we publish a book - we engage in helping others to materialize
their potential. We should always do so willingly and reasonably -
otherwise the contracts that we sign will be null and void. But to deny
anyone his capacity to materialize his potential and the goods and services
that he needs to do so - after a valid contract was entered into - is
immoral. To prevent a service or to condition it (Mother: I will provide
the goods and services that I agreed to provide to this foetus under this
contract only if and when I will benefit from such provision) is a violation
of the contract and should be penalized. Admittedly, at times we have a
right to choose the immoral (because it has not been codified as illegal) -
but that does not turn it into a moral choice.
Still, not every immoral act involving the termination of life can be
classified as murder. Phenomenology is deceiving: the acts look the same
(cessation of life functions, the prevention of a future). But murder is
the intentional termination of the life of a human who possesses, at the
moment of death, a consciousness (and, in most cases, a free will,
especially the will not to die). Abortion is the intentional termination of
a life which have the potential to develop into a person with consciousness
and free will. Philosophically, no identity can be established between
potential and actuality. The destruction of paints and cloth is not
tantamount (not to say identical) to the destruction of a painting by Van
Gogh, made up of these very elements. Paints and cloth are converted to a
painting through the intermediacy and agency of the Painter. A cluster of
cells a human makes through the agency of Nature. Surely, the destruction
of the painting materials constitutes an offence against the Painter. In
the same way, the destruction of the foetus constitutes an offence against
Nature. But there is no denying that in both cases, no finished product was
eliminated. Naturally, this becomes less and less so (the severity of the
terminating act increases) as the process of creation advances.
Classifying an abortion as murder poses numerous and insurmountable
philosophical problems.
No one disputes the now common view that the main crime committed in
aborting a pregnancy - is a crime against potentialities. If so, what is
the philosophical difference between aborting a foetus and destroying a
sperm and an egg? These two contain all the information (=all the
potential) and their destruction is philosophically no less grave than the
destruction of a foetus. The destruction of an egg and a sperm is even more
serious philosophically: the creation of a foetus limits the set of all
potentials embedded in the genetic material. The egg and sperm can be
compared to the famous wave function (state vector) in quantum mechanics -
incorporating millions of potential states. The foetus is the collapse of
the wave function: it represents a much more limited set of potentials. If
killing an embryo is murder because of the elimination of potentials - what
should we say about the intentional elimination of many more potentials
through masturbation and contraception?
The argument that it is difficult to say which sperm cell will impregnate
the egg is not serious. Biologically, it does not matter - they all carry
the same genetic content. Moreover, would this counter-argument still hold
if, in the future, we will be able to identify the chosen one and eliminate
only it? In many religions (Catholicism) contraception is murder. In
Judaism, masturbation is "the corruption of the seed" and such a serious
offence that it is punishable by the strongest religious punishment: eternal
ex-communication ("Karet").
If abortion is indeed murder what should be the answers to the following
moral dilemmas and questions (some of them patently absurd):
Is a natural abortion the equivalent of manslaughter (through negligence)?
Do habits like smoking, drug addiction, vegetarianism - infringe upon the
right to life of the embryo? Do they constitute a violation of the
contract?
Reductio ad absurdum: if, in the far future, research will unequivocally
prove that listening to a certain kind of music or entertaining certain
thoughts seriously hampers the embryonic development - should we apply
censorship to the Mother?
Should force majeure clauses be introduced to the Mother-Embryo pregnancy
contract? will they give the mother the right to cancel the contract? Will
the embryo have a right to terminate the contract? Should the asymmetry
persist: the Mother will have no right to terminate - the embryo will or
vice versa?
Being a rights holder, can the embryo (=the State) litigate against his
Mother or Third Parties (the doctor that aborted him, someone who hit his
mother and brought about a natural abortion) even after he died, living no
heirs (except the plaintiffs)?
Should anyone who knew about an abortion be considered an accomplice to
murder?
If abortion is murder - why punish it so mildly? Why is it that there is a
debate raging on regarding this question? "Thou shalt not kill" is a
natural law, it appears in virtually every legal system. It is easily and
immediately identifiable. The fact that abortion does not "enjoy" the same
treatment says a lot.


The Basic Dilemma of the Artist
By: Dr. Sam Vaknin

The psychophysical problem is long standing and, probably, intractable.

We have a corporeal body. It is a physical entity, subject to all the laws
of physics. Yet, we experience ourselves, our internal lives, external
events in a manner which provokes us to postulate the existence of a
corresponding, non-physical ontos, entity. This corresponding entity
ostensibly incorporates a dimension of our being which, in principle, can
never be tackled with the instruments and the formal logic of science.

A compromise was proposed long ago : the soul is nothing but our self
awareness or the way that we experience ourselves. But this is a flawed
solution. It is flawed because it assumes that the human experience is
uniform, unequivocal and identical. It might well be so - but there is no
methodologically rigorous way of proving it. We have no way to objectively
ascertain that all of us experience pain in the same manner or that pain
that we experience is the same in all of us. This is even when the causes of
the sensation are carefully controlled and monitored.

A scientist might say that it is only a matter of time before we find the
exact part of the brain which is responsible for the specific pain in our
gedankenexperiment. Moreover, will add our gedankenscientist, in due course,
science will even be able to demonstrate a monovalent relationship between a
pattern of brain activity in situ and the aforementioned pain. In other
words, the scientific claim is that the patterns of brain activity ARE the
pain itself.

Such an argument is, prima facie, inadmissible. The fact that two events
coincide (even if they do so forever) does not make them identical. The
serial occurrence of two events does not make one of them the cause and the
other the effect, as is well known. Similarly, the contemporaneous
occurrence of two events only means that they are correlated. A correlate is
not an alter ego. It is not an aspect of the same event. The brain activity
is what appears WHEN pain happens - it by no means follows that it IS the
pain itself.

A stronger argument would crystallize if it was convincingly and repeatedly
demonstrated that playing back these patterns of brain activity induces the
same pain. Even in such a case, we would be talking about cause and effect
rather than identity of pain and its correlate in the brain.

The gap is even bigger when we try to apply natural languages to the
description of emotions and sensations. This seems close to impossible. How
can one even half accurately communicate one's anguish, love, fear, or
desire ? We are prisoners in the universe of our emotions, never to emerge
and the weapons of language are useless. Each one of us develops his or her
own, idiosyncratic, unique emotional language. It is not a jargon, or a
dialect because it cannot be translated or communicated. No dictionary can
ever be constructed to bridge this lingual gap. In principle, experience is
incommunicable. People - in the very far future - may be able to harbour the
same emotions, chemically or otherwise induced in them. One brain could
directly take over another and make it feel the same. Yet, even then these
experiences will not be communicable and we will have no way available to us
to compare and decide whether there was an identity of sensations or of
emotions.

Still, when we say "sadness", we all seem to understand what we are talking
about. In the remotest and furthest reaches of the earth people share this
feeling of being sad. The feeling might be evoked by disparate
circumstances - yet, we all seem to share some basic element of "being sad".
So, what is this element?

We have already said that we are confined to using idiosyncratic emotional
languages and that no dictionary is possible between them.

Now we will postulate the existence of a meta language. This is a language
common to all humans, indeed, it seems to be the language of being human.
Emotions are but phrases in this language. This language must exist -
otherwise all communication between humans would have ceased to exist. It
would appear that the relationship between this universal language and the
idiosyncratic, individualistic languages is a relation of correlation. Pain
is correlated to brain activity, on the one hand - and to this universal
language, on the other. We would, therefore, tend to parsimoniously assume
that the two correlates are but one and the same. In other words, it may
well be that the brain activity which "goes together" is but the physical
manifestation of the meta-lingual element "PAIN". We feel pain and this is
our experience, unique, incommunicable, expressed solely in our
idiosyncratic language.

We know that we are feeling pain and we communicate it to others. As we do
so, we use the meta, universal language. The very use (or even the thought
of using) this language provokes the brain activity which is so closely
correlated with pain.

It is important to clarify that the universal language could well be a
physical one. Possibly, even genetic. Nature might have endowed us with this
universal language to improve our chances to survive. The communication of
emotions is of an unparalleled evolutionary importance and a species devoid
of the ability to communicate the existence of pain - would perish. Pain is
our guardian against the perils of our surroundings.

To summarize : we manage our inter-human emotional communication using a

 

 

Go to part:2  3 

 

 

Copyright © 1999 Sam Vaknin
Published on the World Wide Web by "www.storymania.com"